IV. SUMMARY
Out of the ashes of World War
I1 there rose a desire to further define the responsibility of a commander
for war crimes committed by his subordinates, a responsibility recognized
by the earliest military scholars. Although the Tribunals after World War
I1 sought to establish an international norm, there was of necessity much
reliance on domestic standards in resolving questions of knowledge,
responsibility, and negligence; and while the post-World War I1
trials from a legal point of view purportedly have no precedental value,
the codification of many of the principals contained therein by the 1949
Geneva Convention would indicate that from a practical standpoint the
standards formulated are recognized as international norms. All of the law
of war is the formal expression of the principle of restraint; and it is
to the commander, particularly the commander in the field, that the
responsibility for exercise of restraint is most directed, inasmuch as he
has control of both the means of destruction and the means of restraint.
Throughout the history of warfare the commander has received the glories
of victory and the burden of defeat, whether deserved or not.
The role of the commander is a lonely one; its authority may be delegated,
but never its responsibility. In accepting the position of commander, an
officer accepts massive responsibility - responsibility to see that his
troops are fed, clothed, and paid; responsibility for their welfare,
morale, and discipline; responsibility for his unit’s tactical training
and proficiency; responsibility for close coordination and cooperation
with adjacent and supported or supporting units; and responsibility for
accomplishment of his mission. He is no less charged with the
responsibility to accomplish that mission within the limitations of the
laws of war, and to exercise due control over his subordinates to insure
their compliance.
In order to find a commander
responsible, the acts charged must have been committed by troops under his
command. Normally this refers to troops of his unit or of another unit
over which he has both operational and administrative control; but absent
either he may still be responsible if he otherwise had a duty and the
means to control those troops and failed to do so. If he has executive
authority over a specified occupied territory, he is responsible for all
illegal acts occurring within that territory, or at least for controlling
or preventing their occurrence. While exclusion of any one of these
factors may excuse him from liability under international standards, he
may nonetheless be held responsible under domestic standards if he knows
of an offense and, possessed of the duty to respond, fails to do
everything within his power to prevent or report that offense.
In controlling his men, the
commander has a duty to utilize all means available to him to know
of and prevent the occurrence of war crimes within his command. In
particular, he cannot shun or ignore the obvious and plead ignorance as a
defense in an effort to escape liability.
The commander who directly
orders the commission of a war crimes shares the guilt of the perpetrator
of the offense. So, too, does the intermediate commander who receives an
order patently illegal on its face who passes that order to subordinates
for execution, although the plea of superior orders may be heard in
mitigation, a commander may also be held responsible where he does not
necessarily order certain illegal acts but is shown to have encouraged
their perpetration or incited his men to act. Where he has neither ordered
nor incited his men to carry out war crimes, he may be deemed responsible
if by his acts he has acquiesced therein. Only the degree of culpability
may distinguish the commander from the actual perpetrators in the
instances cited above.
Essential to any allegation of
command responsibility is the element of knowledge, either actual
knowledge or the means of knowledge which the commander failed
to exercise. Actual knowledge may be presumed in two instances: (a) where
the commander has executive authority over occupied territory, and
the offenses occur within that territory; and (b) where reports of
offenses are made to his command, the presumption being that such reports
are made for the benefit of the commander. These presumptions may be
rebutted, for example, by a showing of absence from the command at the
time of the offense or its report, or by illness; but this rebuttal is
temporary in nature, extending only for the period of the absence or
illness. Any inaction upon resumption of command raises a presumption of
acquiescence, knowledge again being presumed.
No theory of absolute
liability has found acceptance in either international or domestic law. No
man, whether commander or the lowest private, is held responsible for the
acts of another absent the establishment of some sharing of the mens
rea. The absolute liability theory has been expressly rejected in
every case in which it was argued. Only where there has been wanton,
immoral disregard amounting to acquiescence in the offense has criminal
responsibility attached. The conduct - a wanton disregard of the
occurrence of offenses - must be such as to support a finding that
the commander is an accomplice in the sense that he shared the criminal
intent of his subordinates and that he encouraged their misconduct through
a failure to discover and intervene where he had a duty to prevent their
action. Absent actual knowledge there must be either (1) such serious
personal dereliction on the part of the commander as to constitute wilful
and wanton disregard of the possible consequences; or
(2) an imputation of constructive knowledge, that is, despite pleas
to the contrary the commander under the facts and circumstances of the
particular case must have known of the offenses charged and acquiesced
therein.
In determining whether the
commander either should have known or must have known of the occurrence of
the offenses charged, certain subjective criteria may be considered in an
effort to determine his means of knowledge: (a) the rank of the commander;
(b) the experience of the commander; (e) the training of the men under his
command; (d) the age and experience of the men under his command; (e) the
size of the staff of the commander; (f) the comprehensiveness of the
duties of the staff of the commander; (g) the “sliding probability ratio”
of unit-incident-command; (h) the duties and complexities of the
commander by virtue of the command he held; (i) communications abilities;
(j) mobility of the commander; (k) isolation of the commander; (1)
composition of forces within the command; and (m) the combat situation.
In holding a commander
responsible under international standards, the commander’s acts of
commission or omission must be tantamount to “wanton, immoral disregard”
of the acts of his subordinates. This international standard is consistent
with municipal standards for which the same maximum penalty of death may
be imposed. Where lesser penalties may be exacted, such as for a negligent
failure to discover or report an offense, lesser standards of negligence -
either culpable or simple – are provided. There municipal standards are
defined by the Uniform Code of Military Justice and by duties imposed by
existing orders and regulations; international standards are defined by
existing treaties and conventions, in particular the 1949 Geneva
Conventions which require wilful and wanton conduct in order for there to
be a grave breach of those Conventions. Any further definition must depend
on the facts of the particular case and the previously-discussed
subjective criteria rather than a precisely-defined international
definition. The duty is well established, the responsibility well-defined.
A
contemporary Marine Corps
recruiting poster asserts the principle :
Some men accept
responsibility; others seek it,
Neither the principles of
command nor the law of war can expect, nor accept, anything less.
General Joseph Joffre, who led the French Army in repulsing
the German offensive at the battle of the Marne in 1914, was once
asked who had won that battle-he or his subordinate commander,
Ferdinand Foch. General Joffre replied that he did not know who
had won the battle, “but if it had been lost I know who would have
lost it.” A. VANDEGRIFT
ONCE A MARINE 9 (1964).
|